Spring 2012
MATH 209: Discrete mathematics
Branko Ćurgus


Thursday, May 31, 2012


Thursday, May 24, 2012


Tuesday, May 22, 2012


Friday, May 18, 2012


Thursday, May 17, 2012


Tuesday, May 15, 2012


Friday, May 11, 2012


Thursday, May 10, 2012


Monday, May 7, 2012


Thursday, May 3, 2012


Friday, April 27, 2012


Thursday, April 26, 2012


Monday, April 23, 2012


Friday, April 20, 2012


Monday, April 16, 2012


Friday, April 13, 2012


Thursday, April 12, 2012


Monday, April 9, 2012


Tuesday, April 5, 2012

  1. I did not mention this in class, but it is worth mentioning: If the propositional functions $P(x)$ and $Q(y)$ have the same universe of discourse, then the propositions \[ \bigl(\forall x \ P(x) \bigr) \wedge \bigl(\forall y \ Q(y) \bigr), \quad \forall x \ \bigl( P(x) \wedge Q(x) \bigr), \quad \forall x \ \forall y \ \bigl( P(x) \wedge Q(y) \bigr) \] are all equivalent. Each of these propositions says that all the values of both functions $P(x)$ and $Q(y)$ ($x, y$ in the universe of discourse) are true.
  2. Similarly, if the propositional functions $P(x)$ and $Q(y)$ have the same universe of discourse, then the propositions \[ \bigl(\exists x \ P(x) \bigr) \vee \bigl(\exists y \ Q(y) \bigr), \quad \exists x \ \bigl( P(x) \vee Q(x) \bigr) \quad \exists x \ \exists y \ \bigl( P(x) \vee Q(y) \bigr) \] are all equivalent. Each of these propositions says that among the propositions $P(x)$ and $Q(y)$ ($x, y$ in the universe of discourse) there at least one which is true.
  3. On Tuesday I posted several different ways of stating "there exists a unique $x$ such that $P(x)$ is true" ($\exists ! x \ P(x)$, for short) using quantifiers. I will prove below that the following two statements are equivalent: \[ \exists x \ \forall y \ \Bigl( P(x) \wedge \bigl( P(y) \to (y=x) \bigr) \Bigr), \qquad \exists x \ \forall y \ \bigl( P(y) \leftrightarrow (y=x) \bigr). \]
  4. In this item we observe that for arbitrary $x$ in the universe of discourse \[ P(x) \ \leftrightarrow \ \forall y \ \bigl( (y=x) \to P(y) \bigr). \] It might be easier to see the equivalence if we restate the last biconditional using the negations \[ \neg P(x) \ \leftrightarrow \ \exists y \ \bigl( (y=x) \wedge \neg P(y) \bigr). \] For completeness I mention that here the universe of discourse for $y$ is the same as the universe of discourse for $x$.
  5. Now I will prove the equivalence stated in 3. The proof consists of four equivalences which together prove the equivalence stated in 3. Each equivalence should be clear based on today's items 1 and 4.

    First, today's item 1 implies that the proposition \[ \exists x \ \forall y \ \Bigl( P(x) \wedge \bigl( P(y) \to (y=x) \bigr) \Bigr) \] is equivalent to \[ \exists x \ \Bigl( P(x) \wedge \Bigl( \forall y \ \bigl( P(y) \to (y=x) \bigr) \Bigr) \Bigr). \] Second, today's item 4 implies that the last proposition is equivalent to \[ \exists x \ \Bigl( \Bigl( \forall y \ \bigl( (y=x) \to P(y) \bigr) \Bigr) \wedge \Bigl( \forall y \ \bigl( P(y) \to (y=x) \bigr) \Bigr) \Bigr). \] Third, today's item 1 implies that the last proposition is equivalent to \[ \exists x \ \forall y \ \Bigl( \bigl( (y=x) \to P(y) \bigr) \wedge \bigl( P(y) \to (y=x) \bigr) \Bigr). \] Fourth, the definition of biconditional implies that the last proposition is equivalent to \[ \exists x \ \forall y \ \bigl( P(y) \leftrightarrow (y=x) \bigr). \]
  6. In the book there are several exercises which use the proposition "there exist exactly two values of the variable $x$ such that $P(x)$ is true". One way to express this proposition using quantifiers is the following proposition \[ \exists x \ \exists y \ \forall z \ \Bigl( (x\neq y) \wedge \Bigl( P(z) \leftrightarrow \bigl((z=x) \vee (z=y) \bigr)\Bigr) \Bigr). \]

Tuesday, April 3, 2012


Friday, March 30, 2012


Thursday, March 29, 2012


Tuesday, March 27, 2012